Main
Phi-Theory: Phi-Features Across Modules and Interfaces (Oxford Studies in Theoretical Linguistics)
Phi-Theory: Phi-Features Across Modules and Interfaces (Oxford Studies in Theoretical Linguistics)
Daniel Harbour, David Adger, Susana Bejar
0 /
0
How much do you like this book?
What’s the quality of the file?
Download the book for quality assessment
What’s the quality of the downloaded files?
Phi-features, such as person, number, and gender, present a rare opportunity for syntacticians, morphologists and semanticists to collaborate on a research enterprise in which they all have an equal stake and which they all approach with data and insights from their own fields. This volume is the first to attempt to bring together these different strands and styles of research. It presents the core questions, major results, and new directions of this emergent area of linguistic theory and shows how Phi Theory casts light on the nature of interfaces and the structure of the grammar. The book will interest scholars and students of all aspects of linguistic theory at graduate level and above.
Categories:
Year:
2008
Publisher:
Oxford University Press, USA
Language:
english
Pages:
392
ISBN 10:
0199213763
ISBN 13:
9780199213764
Series:
Oxford Studies in Theoretical Linguistics
File:
PDF, 1.67 MB
Your tags:
Download (pdf, 1.67 MB)
- Open in Browser
- Checking other formats...
- Convert to EPUB
- Convert to FB2
- Convert to MOBI
- Convert to TXT
- Convert to RTF
- Converted file can differ from the original. If possible, download the file in its original format.
Report a problem
This book has a different problem? Report it to us
Check Yes if
Check Yes if
Check Yes if
Check Yes if
you were able to open the file
the file contains a book (comics are also acceptable)
the content of the book is acceptable
Title, Author and Language of the file match the book description. Ignore other fields as they are secondary!
Check No if
Check No if
Check No if
Check No if
- the file is damaged
- the file is DRM protected
- the file is not a book (e.g. executable, xls, html, xml)
- the file is an article
- the file is a book excerpt
- the file is a magazine
- the file is a test blank
- the file is a spam
you believe the content of the book is unacceptable and should be blocked
Title, Author or Language of the file do not match the book description. Ignore other fields.
Are you sure the file is of bad quality? Report about it
Change your answer
Thanks for your participation!
Together we will make our library even better
Together we will make our library even better
The file will be sent to your email address. It may take up to 1-5 minutes before you receive it.
The file will be sent to your Kindle account. It may takes up to 1-5 minutes before you received it.
Please note: you need to verify every book you want to send to your Kindle. Check your mailbox for the verification email from Amazon Kindle.
Please note: you need to verify every book you want to send to your Kindle. Check your mailbox for the verification email from Amazon Kindle.
Conversion to is in progress
Conversion to is failed
You may be interested in Powered by Rec2Me
Related Booklists
0 comments
You can write a book review and share your experiences. Other readers will always be interested in your opinion of the books you've read. Whether you've loved the book or not, if you give your honest and detailed thoughts then people will find new books that are right for them.
1
|
2
|
Phi Theory OXFORD STUDIES IN THEORETICAL LINGUISTICS general editors: David Adger, Queen Mary, University of London; Hagit Borer, University of Southern California. advisory editors: Stephen Anderson, Yale University; Daniel Büring, University of California, Los Angeles; Nomi Erteschik-Shir, Ben-Gurion University; Donka Farkas, University of California, Santa Cruz; Angelika Kratzer, University of Massachusetts, Amherst; Andrew Nevins, Harvard University; Christopher Potts, University of Massachusetts, Amherst; Barry Schein, University of Southern California; Peter Svenonius, University of Tromsø; Moira Yip, University College London. recent titles 10 The Syntax of Aspect: Deriving Thematic and Aspectual Interpretation edited by Nomi Erteschik-Shir and Tova Rapoport 11 Aspects of the Theory of Clitics by Stephen Anderson 12 Canonical Forms in Prosodic Morphology by Laura J. Downing 13 Aspect and Reference Time by Olga Borik 14 Direct Compositionality edited by Chris Barker and Pauline Jacobson 15 A Natural History of Infixation by Alan C. L. Yu 16 Phi Theory: Phi-Features across Modules and Interfaces edited by Daniel Harbour, David Adger, and Susana Béjar 17 French Dislocation: Interpretation, Syntax, Acquisition by Cécile De Cat 18 Inflectional Identity edited by Asaf Bachrach and Andrew Nevins 19 Lexical Plurals by Paolo Acquaviva 20 Adjectives and Adverbs: Syntax, Semantics, and Discourse edited by Louise McNally and Christopher Kennedy published in association with the series The Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Interfaces edited by Gillian Ramchand and Charles Reiss For a complete list of titles published and in preparation for the series, see p. 377. Phi Theory Phi-Features across Modules and Interfaces Edited by DANIEL H A RB OUR, DAVID AD GE R , A N D S U S A NA B É JA R 1 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford ox2 6dp Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwid; e in Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With offices in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York © Editorial matter and organization Daniel Harbour, David Adger, and Susana Béjar 2008 © The chapters their several authors 2008 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published 2008 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose the same condition on any acquirer British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Data available Typeset by SPI Publisher Services, Pondicherry, India Printed in Great Britain on acid-free paper by Biddles Ltd., King’s Lynn, Norfolk _________________ ISBN 978–0–19–921376–4 (hbk.) ISBN 978–0–19–921377–1 (pbk.) 1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2 Contents General Preface Notes on Contributors Abbreviations 1 Why Phi? David Adger and Daniel Harbour vii viii x 1 2 Features on Bound Pronouns Irene Heim 35 3 On the Semantic Markedness of Phi-Features Uli Sauerland 57 4 Phi-Agree and Theta-Related Case Milan Řezáč 83 5 Conditions on Phi-Agree Susana Béjar 130 6 Phi-Feature Competition in Morphology and Syntax Martha McGinnis 155 7 Discontinuous Agreement and the Syntax–Morphology Interface Daniel Harbour 185 8 Third Person Marking in Menominee Jochen Trommer 221 9 When is a Syncretism more than a Syncretism? Heidi Harley 251 10 Where’s Phi? Agreement as a Postsyntactic Operation Jonathan David Bobaljik 295 11 Cross-Modular Parallels in the Study of Phon and Phi Andrew Nevins 329 Feature Index Grammatical Topic Index Language Index 369 371 375 This page intentionally left blank General Preface The theoretical focus of this series is on the interfaces between subcomponents of the human grammatical system and the closely related area of the interfaces between the different subdisciplines of linguistics. The notion of ‘interface’ has become central in grammatical theory (for instance, in Chomsky’s recent Minimalist Program) and in linguistic practice: work on the interfaces between syntax and semantics, syntax and morphology, phonology and phonetics, etc. has led to a deeper understanding of particular linguistic phenomena and of the architecture of the linguistic component of the mind/brain. The series covers interfaces between core components of grammar, including syntax/morphology, syntax/semantics, syntax/phonology, syntax/pragmatics, morphology/phonology, phonology/phonetics, phonetics/speech processing, semantics/pragmatics, intonation/discourse structure, as well as issues in the way that the systems of grammar involving these interface areas are acquired and deployed in use (including language acquisition, language dysfunction, and language processing). It demonstrates, we hope, that proper understandings of particular linguistic phenomena, languages, language groups, or inter-language variations all require reference to interfaces. The series is open to work by linguists of all theoretical persuasions and schools of thought. A main requirement is that authors should write so as to be understood by colleagues in related subfields of linguistics and by scholars in cognate disciplines. The current volume seeks to bring together disparate strands of research on ê-features across the modules of morphology, syntax, and semantics. It also attempts to begin to delineate a programme of research that focuses on the formal properties of these features and what they have to tell us about the nature of the interfaces between grammatical modules. David Adger Hagit Borer Notes on Contributors David Adger is Professor of Linguistics at Queen Mary, University of London. He is author of Core Syntax (OUP 2003) and co-editor of the journal Syntax. He has published in various journals including Language, Linguistic Inquiry, and Natural Language and Linguistic Theory on syntax and its interfaces with other components of the grammar. Susana Béjar is a lecturer at the University of Toronto. Her research investigates complexity in morphosyntactic systems. She has published in Syntax and Revue québecoise de linguistique and has a forthcoming book on ê-features with OUP. Jonathan David Bobaljik is a professor of linguistics at the University of Connecticut. He has written widely on aspects of syntax, morphology, and the relationship between them. His publications have appeared in the journals Linguistic Inquiry, Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, and Journal of Linguistics. Daniel Harbour is a lecturer at Queen Mary, University of London. His primary research interest is features, from interpretation to pronunciation. His book publications include Morphosemantic Number (Springer 2007) and his articles have appeared in Syntax and Natural Language and Linguistic Theory. Heidi Harley is an associate professor of linguistics at the University of Arizona. She has interests in morphology and the syntactic representation of event and argument structure. Her publications include English Words: A Linguistic Introduction (Blackwell 2006) and papers in the journals Language, Linguistic Inquiry and Studia Linguistica. Irene Heim is Professor of Linguistics at MIT and is co-editor of the journal Natural Language Semantics. She has published widely in semantics and is coauthor of Semantics in Generative Grammar (Blackwells 1998). Martha McGinnis is an assistant professor in the Department of Linguistics at the University of Calgary. Her research deals with the architecture of grammar with an empirical focus on argument structure and ê-features. She has published in the journals Linguistic Inquiry and Language. Notes on Contributors ix Andrew Nevins is an assistant professor of linguistics at Harvard University. His research spans topics in phonology, morphophonology, morphology, and syntax, and his publications have appeared in Linguistic Inquiry, Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, and Euskalingua. Milan Řezáč is a postdoctoral researcher at the University of Nantes. He is interested in the syntax of agreement and non-thematic positions. His publications on cyclicity, expletives, and agreement interactions have appeared in such journals as Linguistic Inquiry, Syntax, and Lingua. Uli Sauerland leads a research group at the Center for General Linguistics (ZAS) in Berlin. His publications span syntax, semantics, and pragmatics and have appeared in such journals as Linguistic Inquiry, Natural Language Semantics, and Linguistics and Philosophy. Jochen Trommer is a lecturer at the Institute of Linguistics at the University of Leipzig. His main research areas are theoretical morphology and phonology, especially in Distributed Morphology and Optimality Theory. His publications have appeared in the Yearbook of Morphology and Linguistische Berichte. Abbreviations ˘ Person 1 First person 2 Second person 3 Third person I, II, . . . Class labels (Latin, Tsez) A Transitive agent abs Absolutive acc Accusative act Active addr Addressee agr Agreement aor Aorist appl Applicative particle asp Aspect (particle) ATR Advanced tongue root aux Auxiliary ax Accessory ben Benefactive comit Comitative conj Conjunct cpl Completive D Dative argument dat Dative decl Declarative dem Demonstrative dflt Default dir Direction marker (direct/inverse) Number Abbreviations DL Dative displacement dl Dual dyn Dynamic emph Emphatic erg Ergative evid Evidential ex Exclusive expl Expletive fem Feminine FS Functional Sequence fut Future GB Government and Binding gen Genitive GF Grammatical Function GPSG Generalized Phrase Structure Grammar hab Habitual hon Honorific HPSG Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar i Irrational/inanimate imprs Impersonal impf Imperfect, imperfective in Inclusive inch Inchoative ind Indicative inf Infinitive instr Instrumental intr Intransitive kase Structural case LDA Long-Distance Agreement LFG Lexical Functional Grammar loc Locative lrs Low referential status xi xii Abbreviations masc Masculine mood Mood MP Minimalist Program ms Marked scenario (particle) nact Nonactive neut Neuter nmlz Nominalization nom Nominative npst Nonpast nr Near O Transitive object obl Oblique obv Obviative OT Optimality Theory part Participant pc Paucal PCC Person–Case Constraint pf Perfect, perfective pl Plural pot Potential ppl Participle pres Present pret Preterit prev Preverb prog Progressive pron Pronominal base prox Proximate prt Particle pst Past quot Quotative refl Reflexive RG Relational Grammar Abbreviations S Intransitive subject (structural) SAP Speech Act Participant sg Singular sjnct Subjunctive spkr Speaker subj Subject (syntactic) thm Theme tns Tense top Topic tr Transitive u uninterpretable UG Universal Grammar VI Vocabulary item xiii This page intentionally left blank 1 Why Phi? DAVID AD GER AND DANIEL HARB OUR 1.1 Introduction Phi-features present a rare opportunity for syntacticians, morphologists, and semanticists to collaborate on a research enterprise in which all have an equal stake and which all approach with proprietary data and insights: syntacticians with intervention effects and the theory of Agree, morphologists with patterns of syncretism and hierarchies of person, definiteness, and so on, and semanticists with theories of binding and anaphora and theoretical approaches to the presuppositions and entailments that ê-features engender. Given ê-features’ transmodular relevance, it is inappropriate for syntacticians, semanticists, and morphologists to devise three monomodular accounts of ê-features in their own domains. Rather, the study of Universal Grammar must meet the concerns of all three fields with a single unified account and only an account of transmodular generality can be aptly called Phi Theory. Hence this volume’s subtitle: Phi-features across Modules and Interfaces. These research concerns were guiding questions at the 2004 workshop on ê-features held at McGill University, Montreal. The purpose of the conference was to bring together established and upcoming researchers in the syntax, semantics, and morphology of ê-features and to have them present recent advances of intra- and intermodular interest. The current volume derives from the presentations and discussion of the workshop. In this opening chapter, we situate Phi Theory in Generative Grammar, focusing on the history of ê-features and how recent theoretical developments have given them greater prominence. We are grateful to Jonathan Bobaljik, Paul Elbourne, Andrew Nevins, Jochen Trommer, and two anonymous OUP referees for comments on earlier drafts of this introduction. This volume grew out of a conference funded by the Canadian Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council, with supplementary funding from the School of Modern Languages, Queen Mary, University of London. 2 David Adger and Daniel Harbour Before doing so, a word on what we mean by ê-features. We take ê-features to be those involved in predicate–argument agreement, typically person, number, and gender. Other features, such as those involved in honorification and definiteness also fall within this definition, while case, for example, does not. We will refer to the class of such features as ÷ and to the individual features which make up this class as ê-features. As in any emerging theory, the limits of the empirical domain are not given a priori, and we expect the precise definition of ê-features to emerge only after much more work. This volume is merely a preliminary step in what we hope is a promising direction. In the next sections, we trace a necessarily brief and incomplete history of attempts to tackle the development of a theory of ÷. Because the range of relevant works is enormous, our approach will be to tease out what we see as the major themes that have led to the current situation within transformational approaches to Generative Grammar. Because of the historical nature of this overview, we have organized the discussion into three domains: syntax, semantics, and morphology. However, the common themes that begin to emerge challenge the necessity of treating these domains of enquiry separately, a point taken up in the chapters of this volume. 1.2 Syntax There are currently a number of areas of syntactic research in which ê-features play key roles: the cartographic analysis of verb movement and clitic placement, displaced agreement phenomena, the theory of case and agreement, to name a few (see references in the following subsections). However, the prominence afforded to ê-features in current syntactic theory is a recent phenomenon. Indeed, although agreement, as a general phenomenon, was afforded a syntactic treatment very early in generative work, it took a long time for attention to be paid to the properties of the linguistic items that entered into agreement. There were two major impediments to the development of a Phi Theory: lack of appreciation of the relevance of ÷ for syntactic theory in general, and lack of a robust theory of features. Syntactic concern tended to concentrate on the extent to which agreement processes could be assimilated to general syntactic mechanisms, while the substance of what did the agreeing, the internal nature of ÷, was largely ignored. Nevertheless, as we trace the history of topics where properties of agreement were argued to be syntactically relevant, we see that attempts to fine-tune the syntactic debate led naturally to efforts to articulate what the inventory of ê-features is and how their organization impacts on syntactic operations. Why Phi? 3 It did not take long for generative research to reach the idea that ÷, the substance of agreement, was composed of features and that these were manipulated by the syntax. Initially, in Syntactic Structures (Chomsky 1957), agreement was treated as a context-sensitive transformation, converting one category into another. For English subject agreement, this took the form: (1) Number Transformation—obligatory (Chomsky 1957: 112) Structural Analysis: X–C–Y⎧ ⎫ ⎨ S in the Context NPsing – ⎬ Structural Change: C → Ø in other contexts ⎩ ⎭ past in any context The idea is that the inflectional component of non-past sentences is rewritten as the morpheme S in the context of a singular NP, but as zero elsewhere. The notion of “singular NP” is technically dealt with via an atomic symbol, although this is clearly unsatisfactory, a placeholder for further analysis. The S morpheme undergoes morphophonological rules to surface as the appropriate form: /s/, /z/, /-iz/. (Clearly, more irregular alternations, be∼is, have∼has, will require special provision.) This structural change transformation is, in essence, a rewrite rule, belonging primarily to the part of the grammar that specifies how the pronunciation of syntactic structures is effected (cf. Bobaljik, this volume). By the time of Aspects of the Theory of Syntax (Chomsky 1965), however, the approach to agreement had become both featural and syntactic. Two pieces of work fed into this change of perspective. First, a fully transformational account was offered by Postal (1966). Postal suggested that a Spanish noun phrase like unos alumnos “some students” consisting of a determiner and a head noun had the representation: (2) [NP [Article un] [Noun [Stem alumn] [Affix [Gender M] [Number Pl]]]] An obligatory transformation copies the nominal affix to the determiner: (3) [NP [Article un [Affix [Gender M] [Number Pl]]] [Noun [Stem alumn][Affix [Gender M] [Number Pl]]]] This receives the appropriate spellout after the morphophonological rules have applied: (4) [NP [Article un[Affix [o]s]] [Noun [Stem alumn][Affix [o]s]]] = unos alumnos 4 David Adger and Daniel Harbour Second, Harman (1963) had begun to exploit in the syntax the descriptive power afforded by symbols that were internally complex. Chomsky (1965) combined these approaches by positing an N node that branches into a feature matrix containing various features, such as gender, number, case: (5) ⎤ ⎡ +N · gender ⎢· gender ⎥ ⎥ Article →⎣‚ number⎦/__ · · ·⎢ ⎣‚ number⎦, where [Article . . . N] is an NP „ case „ case ⎡ ⎤ This rule assigns the features of the noun to the article, effectively restating Postal’s analysis with features rather than morphemes. Such feature matrices could then be matched with lexical items. The structure of these features was modeled along the lines of the structure of phonological features, as motivated by Halle in a number of publications following work by Jakobson (Halle 1962, Jakobson, Fant, and Halle 1963). This approach places ê-features squarely in the syntax: they undergo syntactic operations triggered by their positioning in syntactic structures. However, the goal in Aspects was to provide an account for the phenomenon of agreement generally. There was no interest in developing a theory of the individual components of agreement. Following Aspects, little more attention was paid to the development of a theory of ÷. In fact, as Gazdar, Klein, Pullum, and Sag (1985: 18) observe: But [after Aspects of the Theory of Syntax], development in the theory of syntactic features basically stopped. Although generative grammarians continued to assume features in their descriptive apparatus, hardly any generative grammarians attempted to give syntactic features the kind of well-defined formal underpinnings that, say, the theory of phrase structure rewriting rules had. George Lakoff ’s 1965 dissertation (published as Lakoff 1970) was an honorable exception, but it influenced the field more toward the development of abstract deep structures and complex transformational derivations than toward appropriate exploitation of features in phrase structure description, despite the rich proposals for feature analysis that it presented. They conclude that “the theory of features fell gradually into a state of chaos.” For their own part, during the 1980s, Gazdar, Klein, Pullum and Sag did provide a theory of features in Generalized Phrase Structure Grammar in the context of which a theory of ê-features could have been developed. However, the ê-features that they themselves posited merely recapitulated the traditional descriptive labels (e.g., PLU, +/− for plural∼non-plural, PER, 1/2/3 for first∼second∼third person) and so did not provide any deep insight into ÷ itself. The same tendency held sway in the Government and Why Phi? 5 Binding tradition (e.g., Lumsden 1987) and in Lexical Functional Grammar (Bresnan 1982). However, if the field was in chaos with respect to its views of features, the chaos was neither total, nor uncreative. Notably, Muysken and van Riemsdijk (1986: vii) observed: Syntactic features have played a somewhat marginal role in the development of the theory of grammar over the past fifteen or twenty years. Even basic questions such as “how many are there?”, “what are they?”, “how do they distribute over syntactic structures?” were hardly addressed, let alone answered. Nevertheless, it is clear that syntactic features do play an important role in syntax. Few, if any, grammarians today hold, that syntactic categories are unanalyzable atomic primitives, and any additional intrinsic properties of syntactic categories are expressed in the form of features. It would appear to be high time, therefore, to examine the theory of syntactic features in a more systematic way. Moreover, Muysken and van Riemsdijk recognized ÷ as a potential source of enlightenment in this domain. Indeed, of the several strands of research that were eventually to place ê-features in a prominent position in syntactic theory, they recognized two: the notion of rich agreement (Taraldsen 1980, Rizzi 1982), and hierarchies of case marking (Silverstein 1976 [1986]). They also drew attention to another work of this period, that was eventually to have major influence (Hale 1973; see Section 1.4 below.) In the twenty years since Muysken and van Riemsdijk’s volume, four major strands of syntactic research have conspired to place ê-features in a position of prominence. The first and second—work on the pro-drop parameter and then, later, on height of verb movement—led to a concept of “rich agreement”, the eventual explication of which has naturally fed into questions about the nature of ÷. Third, the role of case in argument licensing has inspired research into the mechanisms of case and agreement. This, in turn, has led to notions of ê-completeness versus ê-defectiveness, notions that can only be fully justified in the context of an explicit Phi Theory. Fourth, the Person Case Constraint—the impossibility of certain ê-feature combinations in multiple agreement/clitic systems—has recently received much attention as attempts are made to reduce it to other syntactic phenomena. In the subsections that follow, we review these developments and highlight key contributions, conjectures, and results. 1.2.1 Rich agreement The importance of rich agreement was first noted in regard to pro-drop (Taraldsen 1980). Essentially, in languages, like Italian and Greek, where the 6 David Adger and Daniel Harbour verb reveals the person and number of the subject, pro-drop is possible; in languages where it only partially reveals it, such as German and English, it is not. The descriptive generalization is that when agreement is “rich”, it licenses a null subject. The internal richness of Agr, that is, how much information is specified in Agr, became crucial to later analyses of subject pro-drop (Rizzi 1982), and of the generalized pro-drop found in polysynthetic languages (Jelinek 1984). Curiously, however, little attention was paid to what the featural composition of Agr actually was and how it related to the intuitive notion of rich agreement. However, following Emonds (1978) and then, especially, Pollock (1989), it was noted that rich agreement potentially correlated with height of verb movement: for instance, Romance finite verbs, which show rich agreement, move higher than both English finite verbs and Romance participles, which agree less fully. The idea was thoroughly explored for a wide variety of Germanic languages (beginning with a series of works by Platzack and Holmberg, e.g., 1989). This led to attempts to show two things: on the synchronic side, that Germanic languages that had retained verb movement possessed correspondingly richer subject agreement (see, especially, Rohrbacher 1994); on the diachronic side, that the decline of subject agreement and verb movement proceeded in tandem (e.g., Roberts 1985). This work ultimately failed to shed light on the nature of ê-features per se, though, for two reasons. First, the biconditional correlation between rich agreement and verb movement proved to be too strong (see Bobaljik 2003 for thorough overview and formulation of a weaker generalization). Second, it focused on the paradigm, rather than the ê-features that generate paradigms, as the basic explanatory unit in terms of which richness was to be explicated. Despite these failings, the research program did succeed in placing ÷-related morphosyntax center stage. In addition, the research program stemming from Pollock’s work, which used the different landing positions of verbs in French and English to argue for a splitting of I(NFL) into separate tense and agreement projections, progressed to more fine-grained decompositions. For instance, Shlonsky (1989) argued, on the basis of Modern Hebrew (morpho)syntax, for separate PersonP, NumberP, and GenderP (see Linn and Rosen 2003 for similar arguments based on Euchee); and Poletto (2000) argued, on the basis of the distribution of subject clitics (SCL) in Northern Italian dialects, for a structure that splits the person features into separate projections: (6) [NegP [NumP SCL [HearerP SCL [SpeakerP V [TP . . .]]]]] (Poletto 2000: 31) Why Phi? 7 Here we see the connection between syntactic position and richness of agreement captured by projecting ê-features as parts of the basic clausal backbone. Another vein of research where ê-features are claimed to have a presence in the extended projection of the clause involves the fine structure of the left periphery (Rizzi 1997): like IP, CP has come to be decomposed into several different projections and some researchers have argued for relationships between these and various ÷-categories. The general viewpoint taken is that personlike features are represented on high C-domain heads that encode whether sources of knowledge, opinion or belief are shared between the speaker and other discourse participants. This idea has been used to capture a wide range of data, from evidentiality and logophors (Speas 2004, Tsoulas and Kural 1999) to long-distance binding (Sigurðsson 2004) and person hierarchies (Bianchi 2006). 1.2.2 Agreement and case We can see the general approach to the connection between ê-features and case licensing emerge in Lectures on Government and Binding (Chomsky 1981), which influenced much work afterwards. There, what was important once again, however, was the feature bundle Agr, which was implicated in theories of case and government. Agr was assumed to work as a single syntactic unit, just as in the original approaches to the role of rich Agr in licensing null subjects discussed directly above. This approach to Case and syntactic licensing allowed a fairly successful implementation of an important generalization connecting Case and êfeatures: overt subjects with nominative case are restricted to clauses specified with tense and agreement features (that is, finite clauses). Within the Government and Binding framework, this idea was captured by the following kind of specification (see Chomsky 1981): (7) I[+tense +Agr] assigns nominative case to its specifier Note that Agr is itself taken to be a feature here. The plus value may be taken as suggesting a specification of ê-features, though none in particular are mentioned. This proposal now extends naturally to a potential challenge for the original generalization which is raised by languages like European Portuguese, where a nominative subject is, in fact, possible in an infinitive just when the infinitive is inflected for agreement (see Raposo 1987 for Portuguese, and George and Kornfilt 1981 for similar data from Turkish inflected gerunds): 8 David Adger and Daniel Harbour (8) É correto nós ignor-ar-mos isto. Is right us-nom ignore-inf-1pl this “It is right for us to ignore this.” We can capture the data by assuming that the following holds universally: (9) [+Agr] assigns nominative case to its specifier Other analyses treating Agr itself as a feature are Haegeman’s (1986) treatment of West Flemish subject licensing, and, later, Rizzi’s (1990) theory of whmovement, where it was used to explain the possibility of subject extraction after certain complementizers. Throughout this period, no attempt was made to explain the features that comprised Agr or to explicate the notion of rich Agr, [+Agr], in terms of a given inventory of ê-features. As discussed in Section 1.2.1, it was not until the work of Platzack and Holmberg (1989) and Rohrbacher (1994), that there was an attempt to explicate the meaning of [+Agr] in terms of properties of the agreeing verbs: essentially, in terms of how many of a language’s pronominal categories corresponded to unique agreement affixes (see also Vikner 1995). As previously mentioned, Pollock (1989) argued that apparently atomic syntactic categories should be split into their constituent features. Moreover, these features themselves should project as heads which could act as landing sites for verb movement, giving the following clause structure: (10) TP Subject T T AgrP Subject Agr Agr VP V Object Belletti (1990), on the basis of pursuing a transparent relationship between the internal morphological structure of words, and the syntactic structure of Why Phi? 9 clauses (the Mirror Principle of Baker 1988), suggested that AgrP selects TP rather than the structure in (10), while Chomsky (1989) suggested that there were two AgrPs, one below T, which is associated with object agreement, and one above, associated with subject agreement: (11) AgrP Subject Agr Agr TP Subject T T AgrP Agr Object Agr VP V Object This enriched system allowed a more general approach to case assignment, and Chomsky (1993) proposed that structural Case in general is checked in the specifier of Agr heads. Each Agr acted as a “mediator” for the case features of the heads of the phrases they selected (TP and VP). Structural Case checking can then be seen as arising from an agreement relation. However, there were a number of conceptual arguments against the projection of Agr heads in clause structure. In The Minimalist Program, Chomsky (1995, chapter 4) argued that heads which project without semantic effects, such as Agr, should be dispensed with. His alternative suggestion for maintaining the link between ê-features and Case comes from investigations into the syntax of argument structure (especially Hale and Keyser 1993). He proposes that subjects are introduced by a functional head, v (Chomsky 1995: 315 and references therein; see also Kratzer 1996 among many others). This head can 10 David Adger and Daniel Harbour be endowed with ê-features and hence accusative case checking capabilities. Similarly, T is endowed with ê-features that Case license the subject, which itself moves to T’s specifier: TP (12) Subject T T− ê vP Subject v v− ê V v VP V Object In more recent versions of the Minimalist Program, Chomsky (2001) has maintained the intuitive link between agreement and structural Case checking, however, he has made proposals for ê-features themselves. Specifically, person and number features play distinct roles in structural Case checking: when one is absent from a head, the head is defective and Case checking is impossible (this is how he analyses the non-finite T of raising constructions). The idea that the separate features that make up ÷ act independently in the syntax has been developed in analyses of complex agreement phenomena. These analyses differ from the work discussed above in that their focus is not the connection between Case and agreement, but a general theory of the syntactic dependencies established by the operation Agree (Chomsky 2000). An example of such work is Béjar (2004), which investigates the classical problem of Georgian agreement, where the controller of agreement on the verb is not determined by syntactic position or grammatical function, but rather by ê-featural richness. Béjar concentrates on examples which show that person agreement on a verb can arise from one argument whereas number agreement comes from another. For example, in (13), the second person singular object Why Phi? 11 triggers person agreement and the first person plural subject triggers number agreement: (13) g- k’lav-t 2sg-kill- pl “We kill you (singular).” (Hewitt 1995: 132) This kind of agreement has been treated morphologically in the past (Anderson 1992, Halle and Marantz 1993). Béjar argues that a more satisfying explanation is available when one allows the features within one ÷-set to establish disjoint Agree relations separately in the syntax, and she extends this basic idea to a general analysis of what she terms “agreement displacement phenomena” (see also Řezáč 2003, and for earlier ideas along the same lines Ritter 1995 and Taraldsen 1995). 1.2.3 Person Case Constraint The theories of Case and agreement come together in a single grammatical phenomenon that has proved to be a very productive domain of application and refinement of the theory of ê-features in recent years: the Person Case Constraint. Perlmutter (1971) observed an intriguing restriction on the combination of dative and accusative clitics in Spanish: the accusative in such a situation must be third person. This constraint is known in the literature as the *me lui Constraint, or Person Case Constraint (PCC). We give here an example from French (see Anagnostopoulou 2003 and Haspelmath 2004 for many other cases): (14) a. Agnès me la présentera. Agnès 1sg 3sg.fem present.fut.3sg “Agnès will introduce her to me.” b. *Agnès me lui présentera. Agnès 1sg 3sg.fem present.fut.3sg “Agnès will introduce me to her.” c. Agnès me présentera à elle. Agnès 1sg present.fut.3sg to her “Agnès will introduce me to her.” Example (14a) shows that dative and accusative clitics may cooccur. However, such combinations are only licit if the accusative is third person, hence the contrast between (14a) and (14b). In French, such argument combinations can only be expressed periphrastically, as in (14c). 12 David Adger and Daniel Harbour Bonet (1991) gives a tentative approach to this phenomenon (developed more fully in Bonet 1994) which uses a filter to block the morphological realization of non-third person accusatives in the presence of dative clitics. However, more recently, there have appeared a range of syntactic analyses of the PCC, which crucially appeal to the various ê-features that make up agreement. These approaches have attempted to connect the PCC to various other phenomena. For example, Boeckx (2000) and Anagnostopoulou (2003) have proposed that it is connected to the restrictions on the appearance of first and second person nominative objects in Icelandic; Richards (2005) connects it with cross-clausal extraction in Tagalog; Bianchi (2006) connects it to inverse agreement systems found in languages like Plains Cree and Bobaljik and Branigan (2006), to the Spurious Anti-Passive construction found in Chukchi in configurations that are reminiscent of inverse agreement; Ormazabal and Romero (2002) draw a connection to animacy on the basis of leísta dialects of Spanish, and Adger and Harbour (2007), in a somewhat related vein, have connected it with patterns of case syncretism across different languages. Finally, Nevins (2007), applying, in the syntax, ideas from phonological feature formalisms, comes the closest of any researcher to tackling the full typological variety of the PCC reviewed by Haspelmath in his (2004) crosslinguistic survey of the phenomenon. There is an interesting parallel here with the Georgian agreement effects discussed above: what was once thought to be a paradigm case of a morphological phenomenon can be understood syntactically when we pay attention to the behaviour of the components of ÷ (see especially Béjar and Řezáč 2004 for the impact of the PCC on the theory of Agree). The research displays an exciting lack of consensus, even if some themes are clear: feature structure—whether in terms of competition, or the behaviour of Agree, or the specification of arguments—lies at the heart of these analyses. The sub-÷-structure is crucially implicated in all of these analyses and so a well articulated theory of ê-features is crucial for such work. 1.3 Semantics Although Phi Theory may have taken a time to come into its own in syntax, related issues have enjoyed long attention in semantics. These begin in the philosophico-semantic tradition, in which philosophers aimed to supplement the Fregean and Tarskian theories of formalized languages (Frege 1879, Tarski 1935) for the analysis of natural language (beginning with Frege 1892 and Russell 1905 and leading to the important work of Davidson 1967, Montague Why Phi? 13 1970, 1973, Lewis 1972, which attempted to connect contemporary philosophical semantics with grammatical theory). Key amongst the requisite additions relevant here were notions of indexicality and presuppositionality, and mechanisms for the representation of quantities. We address each of these below. 1.3.1 Indexicality and presuppositionality The category of person was an early focus of research in the philosophy of language. It arose naturally in two regards: first, indexicals (Jespersen’s “shifters”) were an obvious domain that was not embraced by semantic theories designed for the elucidation of mathematics; second, the interest in the logical properties of proper names led naturally to attempts to deal with the semantics of pronouns and deictics (e.g., Russell 1940). The most influential work in the philosophical tradition is that of Kaplan. Kaplan (1977 [1989]) formulated the thesis that indexicals are directly referential, entailing that their semantic value is fixed purely by the context of the speech act and cannot be acted on by logical operators. Recently, a variety of evidence has called this view into question. Schlenker (2003), for instance (see also von Stechow 2003, Anand and Nevins 2004), has argued against the Kaplanian view on the basis of Amharic sentences such as (15), which can be used to describe John’s saying of himself “I am a hero”: (15) on @gna n@-ññ y-il-all John hero be.pf-1sgO 3masc.say-aux.3masc “John says that he is a hero.” (Schlenker 2003: 68) Schlenker demonstrates that the embedded clause in Amharic is not a quotation. This shows, straightforwardly, that the semantic value of “I” is not fixed by the context of utterance, as “I” refers to John, not to whoever utters (15). Schlenker’s own treatment of the semantics of person pursues an idea first developed by Cooper (1983) with respect to gender, namely, that it is presuppositional. To see the intuition, consider the following dialogue: (16) “Tell me about Alex.” “Evidently she’s married: you can see the wedding ring in this photo of her hand.” If the first speaker knows that Alex is a man, it would be impossible to attempt to correct the second speaker by saying “No, she isn’t married”; this would be taken as accepting that Alex is a woman and disagreeing about his/her marital status. So, Alex’s gender does not form part of the assertion in “She’s married”, but rather is a presupposition. This accords with the intuition that “She’s married”, said of a husband, is not false, but infelicitous. 14 David Adger and Daniel Harbour An influential implementation of this idea, which pursues Tarski’s intuition that reference arises via an assignment of values to variables, is Heim and Kratzer’s (1998). They propose that ê-features are syntactically adjoined to pronominals and that their semantic contribution is a presupposition that restricts the range of the assignment of values to variables. For instance, the structure of the pronoun she, say, is: (17) DP DP [thirdperson] [feminine] DP [singular] DP she1 (Heim and Kratzer 1998: 244) The features are partial identity functions (indicated by the colon in (18)). That is, [feminine] maps individuals to themselves (an identity function), subject to the proviso that the individual is female; it is undefined otherwise (hence, a partial function). (18) [[feminine]] = Îx : x is female. x Applying this to “She is married”, we have that the lower nodes of the DP are assigned to Alex, however, when we move up the tree to [feminine], the partial function fails to return a value as Alex is not female. Schlenker applies this kind of approach to person features too. He proposes a meaning for the first person feature so that it is only defined when the pronoun bearing the feature refers to a group which includes the speaker who utters the sentence in the context, and a similar meaning for the second person feature. He then proposes that third person pronouns are essentially chosen as semantic defaults (see also Sauerland, this volume). However, an interesting semantic problem arises on the presuppositional approach to person and gender features, with respect to bound variable readings of personal pronouns. Consider the following example, where gender Why Phi? 15 is relevant: in a coed class, where the only person to have done the assigned homework is Mary, one can say: (19) Only Mary has done her homework. The important fact about such uses of personal pronouns (first noted by Partee 1989 with respect to the first person) is that they can break free of their presuppositions: (19) means, informally, “Look at the set of people who have done their homework: only Mary is in that set”. So, the pronoun “her” does not constrain the statement to hold only of females, contrary to what one would expect given (18). Elements of this debate have thrown light on the complex interplay between semantic, syntactic, and morphological aspects of ê-features (see, for instance, Déchaine and Wiltschko 2002 and Rullman 2004). Several aspects of the debate are discussed by Heim (this volume). In addition to person and gender, another ê-category, number, has been a productive area of philosophical investigation (e.g., Goodman and Quine 1947, Quine 1960). Given that philosophical semantics has its origins in the foundations of mathematics, set theory is, unsurprisingly, frequently used to represent notions of singularity and plurality. An influential version of this is the lattice-theoretic treatment of plurals (Link 1983). The concepts this work introduced have been deployed in the treatment of plurality, masshood, distributivity, collectivity, and a wide range of aspectual phenomena (Krifka 1992, Verkuyl 1993, Schein 1993, Lasersohn 1995, Landman 1996, Doetjes 1997, Chierchia 1998, Ojeda 1998, Winter 2001, amongst others). Interestingly, in contrast to person and gender, no presuppositional account of number has, to our knowledge, been offered (though Heim and Kratzer 1998: 245 suggest the possibility). It may be (Nevins, p.c.) that, if definiteness were incorporated more fully into the treatment of ÷, it would be possible to attribute all presuppositionality effects to definiteness and to simplify the representation of person and gender. The non-presuppositional treatment of number would then be the norm for other ÷-categories. For steps in this direction, see Kratzer (2006). 1.3.2 Agreement: syntactic or semantic? We have seen that person, number, and gender can be treated as presupposition inducing features. However, gender is of two types: semantically contentful and purely grammatical. An obvious issue for the presuppositional approach is whether grammatical gender is amenable to a purely semantic approach. For example, in German, Mädchen “girl” is grammatically neuter, as can be seen from the form of the relative pronoun that it controls: 16 David Adger and Daniel Harbour (20) das Mädchen, das/*die das Buch ließt the.neut girl that.neut/that.fem the book read.pres “the girl who reads the book” The relative pronoun is obligatorily neuter, agreeing with the noun and article. The feminine relative pronoun, required in an example with a grammatically feminine noun such as (21) below, is impossible. (21) die Frau, die/*das das Buch ließt the.fem woman that.fem/that.neut the book read.pres “the woman who reads the book” However, if the girl is referenced by a pronoun, the feminine, rather than the neuter, is used: (22) Das Mädchen sagt, daß sie/*es das Buch ließt. the.neut girl say.pres that she.fem/it.neut the book read.pres “The girl says that she is reading the book.” On the assumption that the pronoun’s function is the semantic one of picking out a referent, these examples appear to show that the neuter agreement that Mädchen “girl” triggers is sensitive to a syntactic rather than a semantic feature. Dowty and Jacobson (1988), however, argue against this idea, as part of a general program to minimize the contribution of syntax, and suggest instead that agreement should be treated as an essentially semantic phenomenon. Pollard and Sag (1994) provide evidence for this approach on the basis of a range of phenomena where simple feature matching in the syntax would give the wrong results. A striking case of this is reference transfer of the following sort (a modification of Nunberg’s 1979 ham sandwich example): (23) The hash browns at table six is/*are getting angry. “The person at table six, who ordered the hash browns, is getting angry.” Here the agreement on the verb seems to be with the referent of the subject, the person who ordered the hash browns, rather than with the syntactic specification of the hash browns. Collective nouns in British English provide further evidence that differences in number agreement correlate with differences in interpretation: (24) The committee has/have voted today. For such dialects, the agreement on the auxiliary correlates with interpretational effects on the subject, independent of singular number marking on Why Phi? 17 the noun. Sauerland and Elbourne (2002) note a number of other semantic phenomena affected by this kind of agreement. The theoretical point made by Dowty and Jacobson is that verbal agreement features can contribute to semantic interpretation. This constitutes a prima facie difficulty for the syntactic approach to agreement outlined above, where agreement on the verb is supposed to lack semantic content. 1.4 Morphology 1.4.1 Precursors Morphology is a natural place to look for a theory of the internal featural constitution of ê-structures. To see why, consider the Tok Pisin pronoun paradigm (Foley 1986: 67): (25) Person 1in 1ex 2 Singular Dual Plural — mi yu yumitupela mitupela yutupela yumi mipela yupela Observe that the meaning/pronunciation of the first person inclusive is the sum of the meaning and pronunciation of its parts: yumi . . . means yu and mi. This suggests that first person inclusive, first person exclusive, and second person are not sui generis, but are composed of more fundamental features. The same conclusion—that traditional categories of description are composites of features—is underlined by number in (25). Observe that the dual, tupela, is the plural, pela, plus something else. Thus, these numbers share part of their meaning, non-singularity, and part of their sound, pela. The phenomenon of syncretism, as discussed by Hale (1973, see also Halle 1997), reveals the same fact about duals and plurals. In Warlpiri, in certain contexts, plural agreement occurs where, on purely semantic grounds, we would expect dual; call these *dl-contexts. Hale accounts for this by supposing that dual is a composite [a b], where [a] means simply non-singular (cf., Tok Pisin pela) and [b] restricts the non-singularity to duality (cf., Tok Pisin tu). What is special about *dl-contexts is that [b] is deleted, making dual [a b] identical with plural [a]. Thus, we see that core morphological phenomena lead quickly to a set of research questions for which the development of a theory of ê-features is 18 David Adger and Daniel Harbour necessary. It is, therefore, surprising to discover that ê-features are all but wholly absent from such volumes as Theoretical Morphology (Hammond and Noonan 1988) and The Handbook of Morphology (Spencer and Zwicky 1998). However, on closer inspection, there are legitimate reasons for this absence. As Spencer and Zwicky observe, morphology was neglected in deference to syntax and phonology in early developments of generative grammar (as we have indicated above, agreement was treated as the result of a rewrite rule or syntactic transformation); only with Halle’s (1973) programmatic statement for a generative theory of morphology did interest begin to center on morphology as research domain in its own right. The Lexicalist interpretation of Chomsky (1970) gave this extra life as the debate about morphology could be cast in terms of the division of labor between the lexicon and syntax (see Borer 1998 for overview). To the extent that the nature of inflection was studied at this time, it was as a means of examining how labor was shared between modules of the grammar. For instance, Anderson (1982) uses agreement in Breton verbs and prepositions to argue that agreement is syntactically autonomous and subject to syntactic processes; it is only due to such processes that the agreement comes to be incorporated into the word of which it ultimately forms part. As such, agreement phenomena were counterexamples to the generalized Lexicalist hypothesis. However, in this context, the internal constituency of êstructures was not overly of interest. Nonetheless, two major precursors to a theory of ê-features did emerge at this time, namely, the above-mentioned Hale (1973) and Silverstein (1986). Both of these works present articulated inventories of ê-features which go beyond the mere “featurization” of traditional grammatical categories, and give thought to what minimal set of features will generate all of the attested categories. In particular, both authors stress the idea that person categories, like the first person inclusive, and number categories, like the dual, are not features in their own right (e.g., [+inclusive] or [+dual]), but are composites of features (in Silverstein’s system, [+ego +tu] and [+plural +restricted]). Hale’s work has been particularly influential for several reasons. He presented analyses of data types that have since become mainstays for the field. For instance, the 1973 paper treats syncretism between morphological categories in a way that prefigures the impoverishment analysis of Bonet (1991) and later authors. Similarly, Hale (1997), versions of which had been in circulation several years earlier, introduced the notion of composed number and emphasized its relevance as an alternative demonstration of the fact that the dual is not a feature in its own right, but an overlap of the feature specification of singular and plural. Why Phi? (26) 19 a. Pam wari. that run.pf “He/she ran.” b. Puma wari. those run.pf “They (two) ran.” c. Puma yùutu. those run.pf “They (plural) ran.” (Hale 1997: 74) Hale’s work has been incorporated into key studies of ÷-structure, especially, Bonet (1991) and Noyer (1992), and into work on morphology in general, most notably, Halle and Marantz (1993) and Halle (1997). 1.4.2 The composition of ÷ In morphology, the onset of Phi Theory proper must be attributed to the two works by Bonet and Noyer just cited. In these, the authors were concerned with issues of what ê-features there are, how they are structured, what operations the morphology can perform on them, and how such operations are constrained. Bonet’s investigation (see also Bonet 1995) was motivated, in large part, by an attempt to account for non-transparent surface outputs in clitic combinations, a topic that (pace Hale 1973) had “hardly received any attention” (Bonet 1991: 10). A classic case of this phenomenon concerns the combination, in Spanish, of the third person masculine singular clitics for indirect and direct objects, respectively, le and lo. When the context demands that the clitics cooccur, they surface, not as le lo, but as se lo. Perlmutter (1971), who first drew attention to the phenomenon in the Generative context, posited what was, essentially, a phonological rewrite rule: ⎡ ⎤⎡ ⎤ (27) PRO PRO ⎣ III ⎦ ⎣ III ⎦ Dat. Acc. 1 2 → se, 2 As Bonet observes, an equally legitimate rule, on this approach, would introduce the syllable ba instead of se; it is coincidental that what emerges when le is prevented from surfacing is another clitic, the reflexive se, rather than any other phonological string. The issue, then, that Bonet investigates is how the ê-structure of le is transformed into that of se. 20 David Adger and Daniel Harbour Bonet’s theory involves several notions that have been key to later developments of morphological Phi Theory. First, she adopts (p. 58) a hierarchical organization of ê-features: (28) First/Second CLITIC ARGUMENT PERSON Third Person Dative CLITIC ARGUMENT OBLIQUE Third Person Accusative CLITIC ARGUMENT Agreement Agreement ([fem]) ([pl]) ([fem]) ([pl]) [±1] Agreement ([pl]) Here, the “defining properties of the clitics” are in small capitals, the agreement features themselves in lowercase. (Bonet is ambivalent as to whether the geometrical feature structure, an idea she attributes to Marantz, constitutes morphological structure in its own right—whether syntax deals in feature bundles that are mapped onto geometrical structures in the morphology—or whether the geometries are simply syntactic structures “pruned” of extraneous information.) The feature structures in (28) serve to constrain morphological operations and to define metrics of markedness and defaulthood. Basically, the more structure, and so features, a ê-set contains, the more marked it is. Bonet accounted for the le lo → se lo neutralization by supposing that morphology can delink lower parts of the structure. In particular, given that the structure for se is a substructure of that for le, delinking the lower part of the le structure reveals the se structure, explaining why le becomes se, rather than any other syllable of the language. Noyer (1992), like Bonet, was concerned with the organization of ê-features and operations on them (see also Noyer 1998). In particular, he proposed the process of Fission, whereby a single syntactic terminal node is split into separate positions for multiple phonological strings (see Harbour, this Why Phi? 21 volume, for an overview of the account). However, he also resumed another theme of research, from Hale (1973) and Silverstein (1976 [1986]), namely, the inventory of ê-features. Investigating a wide variety of languages, some of them in great depth and with great insight, he arrived at two number features [+ _ singular] and [+ _ augmented], and three person features, [+ _ author], [+ _ hearer], and [+ _ participant]. Moreover, Noyer showed that languages do not all use every one of the features in their person/number inventories. For instance, a language with singular, dual, and plural, such as Kiowa (Harbour 2007), uses both number features; a language with just singular and plural, such as Mam (England 1983), uses only [+ _ singular]; and a language with a dual–plural distinction in first person inclusive, and a singular–plural distinction in all other persons, such as Ilocano, uses just [+ _ augmented]. Since Noyer’s work, more extensive typological research has been undertaken with regard both to person and to number (Corbett 2000, Cysouw 2003, Siewierska 2004). And so, it remains to be seen whether Noyer’s inventory of features naturally extends to the cases that he did not directly consider. Not only did Noyer present detailed arguments for the quantity and definitions of his features, but he even argued for the necessity of their bivalence. He did this primarily by appeal to ·-rules, that is, to rules that switch the values of particular features, or that are triggered when pairs of features have opposing values. Most notably, he argued for the bivalence by motivating ·-rules in the treatment of person in Mam and number in Kiowa-Tanoan. This issue has been taken up since by Harley (1994), McGinnis (2005), Harbour (2005), amongst others. The significance of ê-feature valence extends beyond morphology: Béjar’s syntactic treatment of Georgian agreement discussed above crucially relies on the absence of a feature rather than its negative specification; bivalence permits a three-way distinction between assertion, negation, and absence of a property, that is not replicable with privativity, consequently, the two feature notations can be semantically distinguished. So long as number features were assumed to be [singular], [dual], [trial], and so on, that is, mere “featuralization” of traditional descriptive labels, their definition attracted little attention from, and paid little heed to, semantics. A plausible reason for this is that both morphologists and semanticists may have taken semantic methods to be overly complex for the treatment of such apparently simple notions as “one”, “two”, “three”. Such overlap in interest as there was came in the domains of collectives and distributives (e.g., Ojeda 1998 and Corbett 2000) and in pluralities of events (e.g., Mithun 1988 and Lasersohn 1995). However, as work like Noyer’s moves morphological 22 David Adger and Daniel Harbour definitions of number away from the obvious and into the abstract, questions begin to arise concerning the semantic nature of these definitions: are they exclusive to morphology, or are they shared with other semantic systems? Developing Noyer’s system, Harbour (2007) has demonstrated that the primitives that morphologists require in the treatment of complex agreement syncretisms are the same as those semanticists require in the representation of collectivity, distributivity, and basic cardinality (singular, dual, plural). Subsequent investigation (Harbour 2006a, 2006b), building also on semantic work by Krifka (1992), has shown that the formal notions developed in the treatment of aspect are almost exactly the feature definitions required to generate the number systems attested across the world, including even the rarest, incorporating, for instance, unit augmented, or trial, or greater and lesser paucal. 1.5 Markedness Markedness has been a major theme in ê-theory; not only was it addressed by many of the authors mentioned already above (Bonet, Harley, Noyer, Ritter, Silverstein), but it goes back to the earliest work on features by Jakobson and Trubetskoy (Haspelmath 2006 for an overview), and has become a focus of some debate since (e.g., Cowper 2005, Nevins 2007, Sauerland, this volume). Morphologically, one can distinguish “formal” and “functional” markedness (Dixon 1994). Formal markedness concerns, quite simply, whether a form is overtly marked. For instance, for English nouns, the singular is unmarked, the plural marked: compare singular book with plural books. Functional markedness concerns which of a group of grammatical categories is distinguished from the others. For example, within the English pronominal system, nominative and genitive appear only in specialized contexts, while accusative is unmarked, being used for, amongst other things, direct objects, indirect objects, predicates (It’s me), subjects of gerunds, and Jespersen’s (1924) “nexus of deprecation” (Me dance?). There is frequent coincidence between formal and functional markedness. The third person is a well known instance. Silverstein (1976 [1986]: 173) observes a number of pronominalization phenomena in which, although no person is intended, third person forms are used. He concludes that third person is functionally unmarked, whereas first and second are marked. Benveniste, on the other hand, in an often alluded to passage, observes that third person is often formally unmarked: Why Phi? 23 Certain languages show that “third person” is indeed literally a “non-person”. To take just one example among many, here is how the possessive pronominal prefixes are presented in two series (something like inalienable and alienable) in Yuma (California): first person ?-, ?an y -; second person, m-, man y -; third person, zero, n y -. The personal reference is a zero reference outside the I/you relationship. (Benveniste 1971: 221; last ‘-’ added—dah/dja) However, this is far from a perfect correlation, as the English present tense -s for third person singular attests. Given the imperfect correlation between formal and functional markedness, there is debate about what the precise criterion of functional markedness consists of, and, indeed, whether there can be a single criterion of functional markedness, or whether, in fact, it is a cluster of notions (see Haspelmath 2006 for discussion). There are a number of means of representing markedness. At the level of the ê-set, one can regard size of structure (whether a geometry or a feature bundle), as a metric of markedness. Additionally or alternatively, markedness can be attributed to features themselves, rather than to the feature structure. For instance, Harley and Ritter (2002) posit two number features and suppose that one feature is unmarked in the sense that, if a language uses only one feature in its grammar, it will be that feature. Furthermore, if features are bi- or multivalent (Harley and Ritter’s are privative), then markedness can be attributed to feature values, additionally or alternatively to the concept of a feature’s being marked itself. In systems where the feature values are + and −, there is sometimes the assumption made that plus is the marked value and minus the unmarked. Silverstein (1976 [1986]) made an early attempt to maintain this position. Yet, his own analysis shows it to be empirically untenable in its simplest form (see Silverstein, p. 188, on “markedness polarity” and his footnote 9, pp. 227–8). One way to capture context-dependent markedness is by directly encoding it as a feature’s value (Chomsky and Halle 1968). So, a feature, [ÏF], would be specified as marked (m) or unmarked (u), with the eventual +/− value being determined by a rewrite rule which is sensitive to context: (29) m → + in the context [__F] [ÏG] m → − in the context [__F] [ÏH] u → + in the context [__F] [ÏI] u → − in the context [__F] [ÏJ] Lakoff (1970) provides specific arguments, attributed to Postal, in this direction. See also Bierwisch (1967), and more recently Wiese (1999). 24 David Adger and Daniel Harbour The limiting case of markedness is that of the default. Intuitively, if an element has multiple uses, it is relatively unmarked. Default items constitute the most extreme cases of multiplicity of use within a natural class of items. They are negatively defined, informally, as the form used where no other is appropriate. Following on from work by Kiparsky (1973), defaults, or “elsewhere” forms, have been formally accommodated within some theories (e.g., Distributed Morphology, Halle and Marantz 1993). The markedness metrics above, namely size of structure and number of marked values, do not induce a complete ordering on all possible ê-sets: different ê-sets can contain the same number of features and/or marked values. For instance, if ê1 is marked with respect to person and unmarked with respect to number, and ê2 , conversely, by whatever criterion of markedness, then neither exceeds the other in total markedness. One way past this impasse, if one takes total ordering with respect to markedness as a desideratum, is to claim that person and number, for example, are not equally marked, but rather that person is extrinsically more marked than number (in which case, ê1 is more marked than ê2 ). There are some intriguing generalizations in this domain. Both number and gender distinctions are frequently lost with respect to person, but in opposite fashions. Simplifying Corbett (1991, 2000) slightly, if a language makes number distinctions only for some persons, then it will be only for first, or only for first and second (see Siewierska 2004 for some dissent); and if a language makes gender distinctions only for some persons, then it will be only for third, or only for second and third. In other words, in the domain of person, where one tends to find gender, number is rarer, and where one tends to find number, gender is rarer. As for number and gender themselves, Greenberg (1966) observes that no language has more gender distinctions in the plural than in the singular (e.g., German has masculine, feminine, neuter in the singular, but only a common gender in the plural). If we take singular to be the unmarked number, then Greenberg’s discovery is that gender distinctions decrease where number markedness increases. This ties in conceptually with the person facts: where language is most likely to make number distinctions (in first, or first and second person), it is least likely to make gender distinctions. Even if these generalizations do form a conceptually sound cluster, they are tendencies, not universals. A striking example is person/number neutralization in Kuman: person distinctions are lost for some numbers in the (subject) agreement system, but number distinctions are lost for some persons in the pronominal system (Foley 1986: 70, citing Piau 1985): 25 Why Phi? Kuman subject agreement Kuman pronouns Person Singular Dual Plural Person Singular Plural 1 2 3 -i -n -uw -bugl -bit -bit -mun -iw -iw 1 2 3 na ene ye no ene ye Observe that the pattern of subject agreement left, is reminiscent of Greenberg’s generalization concerning gender: fewer person distinctions in the non-singular than in the singular (see Cysouw 2003 for other such cases). Despite the inherent interest of such generalizations, it must be admitted that their precise formulation and how, or whether, they should be captured by a theory of markedness currently evades us. 1.6 Themes in Phi Theory Our focus so far has been on the history of ê-features in the three domains of grammar where they are of primary relevance: syntax, semantics and morphology. However, if this volume is to fulfill its aim of motivating a transmodular Phi Theory, then we require a characterization of the research questions that transcends and unites different modules. Above, we have, of course, noted several places where research themes from different domains of the grammar have converged (the end of Section 1.3 touches on this for syntax and semantics, and the end of Section 1.4 for semantics and morphology, and syntax and morphology). To conclude, we now tie together the emergent issues in Phi Theory in a way that, we hope, will excite further interest whilst serving to emphasize areas where research into modules can be mutually informative, insightful, and stimulating. Questions of science often reduce to three broad issues: substance, structure, and interaction. In Phi Theory, these lead to the following broad themes. Substance What are the different categories of ê-features? Above, we addressed primarily person and number, and secondarily gender (reflecting the foci of the papers in this volume). However, recall that, in syntax, ê-features were simply those that were affected by agreement transformations. Corbett (2006: 133–41) draws attention to a number of other categories that are agreement-like in their behavior: case, definiteness, honorificity, and even, in some languages, some tense/mood/aspect categories (on this last, 26 David Adger and Daniel Harbour see especially, Nordlinger and Sadler 2004). Honorificity, in particular, has received recent attention (Boeckx and Niinuma 2004, Potts and Kawahara 2004, Bobaljik and Yatsushiro 2006). Within each category, what is the inventory of features? That is, what is the inventory of person features, of number features, and so on, and are they universal? Can the same be maintained for gender and honorificity? It is important to emphasize that asking what the inventory of features is is not the same as asking what values of a category are. Consider, for instance, number. A possible value for this category is dual. However, we reviewed above a variety of morphological evidence that suggests that dual is not a primitive feature, but is featurally complex. Moreover, we showed how these number features can be naturally defined given semantic research in the domain of number, aspect, and Aktionsart. Are other familiar ê-categories likewise complex? Structure Within a given ê-category, how are the features structured? Pursuing further the example of number, why can languages have a paucal only if they have a more basic distinction too (Corbett 2000); why can there not be a language with paucal∼non-paucal as its only number distinction? Like questions arise within person (see McGinnis, this volume). Do they arise also within gender? One avenue, mentioned above, is to adopt a geometry, or a filter system. These serve to constrain combinations of features, designating some semantically possible ones as geometrically illicit. However, are geometries and filters themselves submissible to analysis, and, if so, what explains them? Could more careful examination of the syntax or semantics of the features that compose these categories reduce geometries or filters to syntactically or semantically natural conditions? Like questions arise inter- as well as intracategorially. There are a number of well known, if well disputed, correlations between person, number, and gender. For instance, if a language has two different verb forms which move to two different heights, then, if only one has person, that is the verb form that moves higher (Section 1.2.1). Or, no language makes more gender distinctions in the singular than in the non-singular (Section 1.5). Where such constraints concern cooccurrence restrictions, they can clearly be captured by a geometry or filter system. However, these raise again the questions just outlined: what is the origin of the geometry, can it be derived by syntactic or semantic means? The need for syntactic exploration is particularly pressing, given the impact that some of these generalizations have on the syntax (e.g., height of verb movement and clitic placement, or hierarchies and ergative splits). And, if geometric effects can be reduced to Why Phi? 27 questions of syntactic structure, can these, in turn, be derived on semantic grounds? Interaction The questions just outlined begin to touch on issues of interaction between modules: how do module-specific operations interact with the substance and structure of ê-features? On the semantic side, do geometric generalizations stem from demands of the semantic interface, or are they separately stipulated, syntactically or morphologically? How do ê-features interact with the different modes of semantic composition; for instance, do binding and predication treat ê-features on a par (Adger 2005, Kratzer 2006)? On the syntactic side, the core operations are Merge, Move, and Agree. How do ê-features trigger and constrain their application? Can one deduce the nature of feature organization from any such constraints? On the morphological side, do the operations that induce syncretism and allomorphy reveal any hierarchy of ê-features, either organizational or markedness-based? Doubtless, this list of topics and questions is incomplete. However, at this early stage, where Phi Theory is merely emergent, not fully fledged, incompleteness is inevitable. If we are successful in stimulating research into the issues raised, then the future will reveal just how incomplete a picture we have painted. Hopefully, we are not too far off. References Adger, D. (2005). ‘Anaphor/agreement mismatches.’ Paper presented at the Workshop on Binding Theory and Reflexivity, Stuttgart. and D. Harbour (2007). ‘Syntax and syncretisms of the Person Case Constraint’, Syntax, 10: 2–37. Anagnostopoulou, E. (2003). The Syntax of Ditransitives: Evidence from Clitics. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Anand, P., and A. Nevins (2004). ‘Shifty operators in changing contexts’, in R. Young (ed.), Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory 14. Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications, 20–37. Anderson, S. (1982). ‘Where’s morphology?’, Linguistic Inquiry 13: 571–612. (1992). A-morphous Morphology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Baker, M. (1988). Incorporation: a Theory of Grammatical Function Changing. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Béjar, S. (2004). ‘Phi syntax.’ Ph.D. thesis, University of Toronto, Toronto, Canada. and M. Řezáč (2004). ‘Cyclic Agree’. Ms, University of Toronto. Online as LingBuzz 000079 (Google: lingbuzz). Belletti, A. (1990). Generalized Verb Movement: Aspects of Verb Syntax. Turin: Rosemberg & Sellier. 28 David Adger and Daniel Harbour Benveniste, E. (1971). Problems in General Lingustics. Florida: University of Miami Press. Bianchi, V. (2006). ‘On the syntax of personal arguments’, Lingua 116(12): 2023–67. Bierwisch, M. (1967). ‘Syntactic features in morphology: General problems of socalled pronominal inflection in German’, in To Honor Roman Jakobson: Essays on the Occasion of his Seventieth Birthday. The Hague: Mouton, 239–270. Bobaljik, J. (2003). ‘Realizing Germanic inflection: Why morphology does not drive syntax’, Journal of Comparative Germanic Linguistics 6: 129–67. and P. Branigan (2006). ‘Eccentric agreement and multiple Case-checking’, in A. Johns, D. Massam, and J. Ndayiragije (eds.), Ergativity: Emerging Issues. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 44–77. and K. Yatsushiro (2006). ‘Problems with honorification-as-agreement in Japanese: a reply to Boeckx and Niinuma’, Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 24: 355–84. Boeckx, C. (2000). ‘Quirky agreement’, Studia Linguistica 54: 354–80. and F. Niinuma (2004). ‘Conditions on agreement in Japanese’, Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 22: 453–80. Bonet, E. (1991). ‘Morphology after syntax: Pronominal clitics in Romance.’ Ph.D. thesis, MIT, Cambridge, MA. (1994). ‘The person-case constraint: A morphological approach’, in H. Harley and C. Phillips (eds.), The Morphology-Syntax Connection, volume 22. Cambridge, MA: MIT Working Papers in Linguistics, 33–52. (1995). ‘Feature structure of Romance clitics’, Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 13: 607–47. Borer, H. (1998). ‘Morphology and syntax’, in A. Spencer and A. Zwicky, (eds.), The Handbook of Morphology. Oxford: Blackwells, 151–91. Bresnan, J. (ed.) (1982). The Mental Representation of Grammatical Relations. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Chierchia, G. (1998). ‘Plurality of mass nouns and the notion of “semantic parameter” ’, in S. Rothstein (ed.), Events and Grammar. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 53–103. Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic Structures. The Hague: Mouton. (1965). Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (1970). ‘Remarks on nominalization’, in R. A. Jacobs and P. S. Rosenbaum (eds.), Readings in English Transformational Grammar. Waltham, MA: Ginn-Blaisdell, 184–221. (1981). Lectures on Government and Binding. Dordrecht: Foris. (1989). ‘Some notes on the economy of derivation and representation’, in R. Freidin (ed.), Principles and Parameters in Comparative Grammar. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 417–55. (1993). ‘A minimalist program for linguistic theory’, in K. Hale and S. Keyser (eds.), The View from Building 20. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1–52. (1995). The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Why Phi? 29 (2000). ‘Minimalist inquiries: The framework’, in R. Martin, D. Michaels, and J. Uriagereka (eds.), Step by Step: Essays on Minimalist Syntax in Honour of Howard Lasnik. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 89–115. (2001). ‘Derivation by phase’, in M. Kenstowicz (ed.), Ken Hale: A Life in Language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1–52. and M. Halle. (1968). The Sound Pattern of English. New York: Harper and Row. Cooper, R. (1983). Quantification and Syntactic Theory. Dordrecht: Reidel. Corbett, G. (1991). Gender. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (2000). Number. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (2006). Agreement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cowper, E. (2005). ‘A note on number’, Linguistic Inquiry 36: 441–55. Cysouw, M. (2003). The Paradigmatic Structure of Person Marking. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Davidson, D. (1967). ‘Truth and meaning’, Synthèse 17: 304–23, reprinted in D. Davidson (ed.), Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 17–36. Déchaine, R.-M., and M. Wiltschko (2002). ‘Decomposing pronouns’, Linguistic Inquiry 33: 409–42. Dixon, R. M. W. (1994). Ergativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Doetjes, J. (1997). ‘Quantifiers and selection: On the distribution of quantifying expressions in French, Dutch and English.’ Ph.D. thesis, Leiden University, published by HILP. Dowty, D., and P. Jacobson (1988). ‘Agreement as a semantic phenomenon’, in J. Powers and F. de Jong (eds.), Proceedings of the Fifth ESCOL. Ithaca: Cornell Linguistics Club, 95–101. Emonds, J. (1978). ‘The verbal complex V – V in French’, Linguistic Inquiry 9: 151–75. England, N. (1983). A Grammar of Mam, A Mayan Language. Austin, TX: University of Texas Press. Foley, W. (1986). The Papuan Languages of New Guinea. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Frege, G. (1879). Begriffschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens. Halle: Nebert. (1892). ‘On sense and reference’, in Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, volume 100, translated and reprinted in Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, ed. P. Geach and M. Black. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Gazdar, G., E. Klein, G. Pullum, and I. Sag (1985). Generalized Phrase Structure Grammar. Oxford: Blackwells. George, L., and Kornfilt, J. (1981). ‘Finiteness and boundedness in Turkish’, in F. Heny, (ed.), Binding and Filtering. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 105–27. Goodman, N., and W.V.O. Quine (1947). ‘Steps toward a constructive Nominalism’, Journal of Symbolic Logic 12: 105–22. Greenberg, J. H. (1966). Language Universals, with Special Reference to Feature Hierarchies. The Hague: Mouton. 30 David Adger and Daniel Harbour Haegeman, L. (1986). ‘INFL, COMP and nominative case assignment in Flemish infinitivals’, in P. Muysken and H. van Riemsdijk (eds.), Features and Projections. Dordrecht: Foris, 123–37. Hale, K. (1973). ‘Person marking in Walbiri’, in S. R. Anderson and P. Kiparsky (eds.), A Festschrift for Morris Halle. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, Inc, 308–44. (1997). ‘Some observations on the contribution of local languages to linguistic science’, Lingua, 100: 71–89. and S. J. Keyser (1993). ‘On argument structure and the lexical expression of syntactic relations’, in K. Hale and S. J. Keyser (eds.), The View from Building 20. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 53–109. Halle, M. (1962). ‘Phonology in Generative Grammar’, Word 18: 54–72. (1973). ‘Prolegomena to a theory of word formation’, Linguistic Inquiry 4: 3–16. (1997). ‘Distributed Morphology: Impoverishment and fission’, in B. Bruening, Y. Kang, and M. McGinnis (eds.), MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 30: PF: Papers at the Interface. Cambridge, MA: MIT, 425–49. and A. Marantz (1993). ‘Distributed Morphology and the pieces of inflection’, in K. Hale and S. J. Keyser (eds.), The View from Building 20. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 111–176. Hammond, M., and M. Noonan (eds.) (1988). Theoretical Morphology: Approaches in Modern Linguistics. San Diego: Academic Press, Inc. Harbour, D. (2005). ‘Valence and atomic number.’ Ms, Queen Mary, University of London. To appear, Linguistic Inquiry. (2006a). ‘Numerus: Der morphologische Gebrauch semantischer Atome.’ Presentation, Universität Leipzig. (2006b). ‘On the unity of “number” in morphology and semantics’, in R. Otoguro, G. Popova, and A. Spencer (eds.), Essex Research Reports in Linguistics 47 (Proceedings of the York–Essex Morphology Meeting 2). University of Essex: Department of Language and Linguistics, 21–30. (2007). Morphosemantic Number: From Kiowa Noun Classes to UG Number Features. Dordrecht: Springer. Harley, H. (1994). ‘Hug a tree: Deriving the morphosyntactic feature hierarchy’, in A. Carnie and H. Harley, (eds.), MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 21: Papers on Phonology and Morphology. Cambridge, MA: MITWPL, 275–88. and E. Ritter (2002). ‘Person and number in pronouns: A feature-geometric analysis’, Language 78: 482–526. Harman, G. (1963). ‘Generative grammars without transformational rules’, Language 39: 597–616. Haspelmath, M. (2004). ‘Explaining the ditransitive Person-Role Constraint: A usage-based approach’, Constructions 2 (online publication). (2006). ‘Against markedness (and what to replace it with)’, Journal of Linguistics 42: 25–70. Heim, I., and A. Kratzer (1998). Semantics in Generative Grammar. Oxford: Blackwells. Why Phi? 31 Hewitt, G. (1995). Georgian: A Structural Reference Grammar. Amsterdam/ Philadelphia: John Benjamins. Jakobson, R., G. Fant, and M. Halle (1963). Preliminaries to Speech Analysis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Jelinek, E. (1984). ‘Empty categories, case and configurationality’, Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 2: 39–76. Jespersen, O. (1924). The Philosophy of Grammar. London: Allen and Unwin. Kaplan, D. (1977[1989]). ‘Demonstratives’, in J. Almog, J. Perry, and H. Wettstein (eds.), Themes from Kaplan. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 481–563. Kiparsky, P. (1973). ‘ “Elsewhere” in phonology’, in S. R. Anderson and P. Kiparsky (eds.), A Festschrift for Morris Halle. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, Inc, 93–106. Kratzer, A. (1996). ‘Severing the external argument from its verb’, in J. Rooryck and L. Zaring (eds.), Phrase Structure and the Lexicon. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 109–38. (2006). ‘Minimal pronouns: Fake indexicals as windows into the properties of bound variable pronouns.’ Ms, UMass, Amherst. Krifka, M. (1992). ‘Thematic relations as links between nominal reference and temporal constitution’, in I. Sag and A. Szabolcsi (eds.), Lexical matters. Stanford, CA: CSLI, 29–53. Lakoff, G. (1970). Irregularity in Syntax. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston. Landman, F. (1996). ‘Plurality’, in S. Lappin (ed.), The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory. Oxford: Blackwells, 425–58. Lasersohn, P. (1995). Plurality, Conjunction and Events. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Lewis, D. (1972). ‘General semantics’, in D. Davidson and G. Harman (eds.), Semantics of Natural Language. Dordrecht: Reidel, 169–218. Link, G. (1983). ‘The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms: A lattice-theoretical approach’, in R. Bäuerle, C. Schwarze, and A. von Stechow (eds.), Meaning, Use and Interpretation of Language. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 302–23. Linn, M., and S. Rosen (2003). ‘The functional projections of subject splits’, Texas Linguistics Forum, 53: 132–46. Lumsden, J. S. (1987). ‘Syntactic features: Parametric variation in the history of English’. Ph.D. thesis, MIT. McGinnis, M. (2005). ‘On markedness asymmetries in Person and Number’, Language 81: 699–718. Mithun, M. (1988). ‘Lexical categories and the evolution of number marking’, in M. Hammond and M. Noonan (eds.), Theoretical Morphology: Approaches in Modern Linguistics. San Diego: Academic Press, Inc, 211–34. Montague, R. (1970). ‘Universal grammar’, Theoria 36: 373–98. Reprinted in Thomason (1974), 222–47. (1973). ‘The proper treatment of quantification in English’, in K.J.J. Hintikka (ed.), Approaches to Natural Language. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 221–42. Reprinted in Thomason (1974), 247–70. 32 David Adger and Daniel Harbour Muysken, P., and H. van Riemsdijk (1986). Features and Projections. Dordrecht: Foris. Nevins, A. (2005). ‘Contrastive specification of person and number on syntactic arguments.’ Presented at the Workshop on Underspecification in Morphology and Syntax, Cologne, Germany, February 2005. (2005). ‘The representation of third person and its consequences for Person Case effects’, forthcoming Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 25: 273–313. Nordlinger, R., and L. Sadler (2004). ‘Tense beyond the verb: Encoding clausal tense/aspect/mood on nominal dependents’, Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 22: 597–641. Noyer, R. (1992). Features, positions and affixes in autonomous morphological structure. Cambridge, MA: MITWPL. (1998). ‘Impoverishment theory and morphosyntactic markedness’, in D. Brentari, S. Lapointe, and P. Farrell (eds.), Morphology and Its Relation to Phonology and Syntax. Palo Alto: CSLI, 264–85. Nunberg, G. (1979). ‘The non-uniqueness of semantic solutions: Polysemy’, Linguistics and Philosophy 3: 143–84. Ojeda, A. (1998). ‘The semantics of collectives and distributives in Papago,’ Natural Language Semantics 6: 245–70. Ormazabal, J., and J. Romero (2002). ‘Agreement restrictions.’ Ms, University of the Basque Country and University of Alcalá. Partee, B. (1989). ‘Binding implicit variables in quantified contexts’, in C. Wiltshire, R. Graczyk, and B. Music (eds.), Papers from CLS 25. Chicago: Chicago Linguistics Society, 342–56. Perlmutter, D. (1971). Deep and Surface Structure Constraints in Syntax. New York: Holt, Reinhart and Winston. Piau, J. A. (1985). ‘The verbal syntax of Kuman.’ Master’s thesis, Australia National University, Canberra. Platzack, C., and A. Holmberg (1989). ‘The role of AGR and finiteness’, Working Papers in Scandinavian Syntax 43: 51–76. Poletto, C. (2000). The Higher Functional Field: Evidence from Northern Italian Dialects. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pollard, C., and I. Sag (1994). Head Driven Phrase Structure Grammar. Stanford: CSLI. Pollock, J.-Y. (1989). ‘Verb movement, Universal Grammar and the structure of IP’, Linguistic Inquiry 20: 365–424. Postal, P. (1966). ‘On so-called “pronouns” in English’, in F. Dinneen (ed.), Monograph Series on Language and Linguistics, volume 19. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 177–206. Potts, C., and S. Kawahara (2004). ‘Japanese honorifics as emotive definite descriptions’, in K. Watanabe and R. B. Young (eds.), Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory 14. Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications, 235–54. Quine, W.V.O. (1960). Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Why Phi? 33 Raposo, E. (1987). ‘Case theory and Infl-to-Comp: The inflected infinitive in European Portuguese’, Linguistic Inquiry 18: 85–109. Řezáč, M. (2003). ‘The fine structure of cyclic Agree’, Syntax 6: 156–82. Richards, N. (2005). ‘Person–Case effects in Tagalog and the nature of long-distance extraction.’ Ms, MIT. Ritter, E. (1995). ‘On the syntactic category of pronouns and agreement’, Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 13: 405–43. Rizzi, L. (1982). Issues in Italian syntax. Dordrecht: Foris. (1990). Relativized Minimality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (1997). ‘The fine structure of the left periphery’, in L. Haegeman (ed.), Elements of Grammar: Handbook of Generative Syntax. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 281–337. Roberts, I. (1985). ‘Agreement parameters and the development of English auxiliaries’, Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 3: 21–58. Rohrbacher, B. (1994). ‘The Germanic languages and the full paradigm: A theory of V to I raising.’ Ph.D. thesis, UMass, Amherst. Rullman, H. (2004). ‘First and second pronouns as bound variables’, Linguistic Inquiry 35: 159–68. Russell, B. (1905). ‘On denoting’, Mind 14: 479–493. (1940). ‘Egocentric particulars’, in An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth. London: Allen and Unwin, 108–15. Sauerland, U., and P. Elbourne (2002). ‘Total reconstruction, PF movement, and derivational order’, Linguistic Inquiry 33: 283–319. Schein, B. (1993). Plurals and Events. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Schlenker, P. (2003). ‘Indexicality, logophoricity, and plural pronouns’, in J. Lecarme (ed.), Research in Afroasiatic Grammar II (Selected Papers from the Fifth Conference on Afroasiatic Languages, Paris, 2000). Amsterdam: Benjamins, 409–28. Shlonsky, U. (1989). ‘The hierarchical organization of subject verb agreement’. Ms, University of Haifa. Siewierska, A. (2004). Person. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sigurðsson, H. (2004). ‘The syntax of person, tense, and speech features’, Italian Journal of Linguistics / Rivista di Linguistica 16: 219–51. Silverstein, M. (1976[1986]). ‘Hierarchy of features and ergativity’, in P. Muysken and H. van Riemsdijk (eds.), Features and Projections. Dordrecht: Foris, 163–232. Originally published in R. M. W. Dixon (ed.), (1976), Grammatical Categories in Australian Languages. Canberra: Australian Institutes of Aboriginal Studies. Speas, M. (2004). ‘Evidentiality, logophoricity and the syntactic representation of pragmatic features’, Lingua 114: 255–76. Spencer, A., and A. Zwicky (1998). The Handbook of Morphology. Oxford: Blackwells. Stechow, A. von (2003). ‘Binding by verbs’, in M. Kadowaki and S. Kawahara (eds.), Proceedings of NELS 33. Amherst: GLSA, 133–57. Taraldsen, T. (1980). On the Nominative Island Condition, Vacuous Application and the That-Trace Filter. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Linguistics Club. 34 David Adger and Daniel Harbour Taraldsen, T. (1995). ‘On agreement and nominative objects in Icelandic’, in S. Olsen, H. Haider, and S. Vikner (eds.), Studies in Comparative Germanic Syntax. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 307–27. Tarski, A. (1935). ‘Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den formalisierten Sprachen’, Studia Philosophica 1: 261–405. Thomason, R. H. (ed.) (1974). Formal Philosophy: Selected Papers of Richard Montague. New York: Yale University Press. Tsoulas, G., and M. Kural (1999). ‘Indexical pronouns as bound variables’, in S. Bird, A. Carnie, J. Haugen, and P. Norquest (eds.), Proceedings of WCCFL 18. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press, 545–57. Verkuyl, H. J. (1993). A Theory of Aspectuality: The Interaction between Temporal and Atemporal Structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Vikner, S. (1995). Verb Movement and Expletive Subjects in the Germanic Languages. New York: Oxford University Press. Wiese, B. (1999). ‘Unterspezifizierte Paradigmen: Form und Funktion in der pronominalen Deklination’, Linguistik Online 4 <http://www.linguistik-online.de/ 3_99/wiese.html>. Winter, Y. (2001). Flexibility Principles in Boolean Semantics: Coordination, Plurality, and Scope in Natural Language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 2 Features on Bound Pronouns IRENE HEIM Are person, number, and gender features on bound-variable pronouns semantically interpreted, or are they just a superficial reflex of agreement between the pronoun and its antecedent? Some have argued that at least some pronouns have the semantics of featureless, unrestricted, variables. Others have pointed out good predictions from the assumption that features on bound pronouns restrict the range of the relevant variable. It has also been suggested in recent work that simple deletion or copying rules such as those proposed in the literature do not quite succeed in predicting the distribution of features on bound pronouns. I will review the case for uninterpreted features and explore some of the challenges involved in improving on existing accounts. Data about plural pronouns with split antecedents will play an important role. 2.1 Phi-features as presupposition triggers Before we debate whether features on bound pronouns are semantically interpreted, we must agree on how they would be interpreted if they were. Uncontroversially, some occurrences of pronoun features are interpreted, notably those on deictic pronouns. Let us make precise what their interpretation in these uncontroversial cases is, so we know what the facts would be like if features on bound pronouns were interpreted likewise. 2.1.1 Features on deictic pronouns The features we are concerned with are the so-called “ê-features”: person, number, and gender. Semanticists that have attended to them have generally given them a presuppositional semantics, as pioneered by Cooper (1983) for English gender. In the implementation of Heim and Kratzer (1998), this looks as follows. In the syntax (LF), each pronoun has a numerical index. Indices are variables and mapped to semantic values by an assignment. For free pronouns, 36 Irene Heim the relevant assignment is given by the utterance context and represents the speaker’s referential intentions. When ê-features are disregarded, the index is the only semantically interpreted part of the pronoun, and the pronoun is simply a variable, as reflected in rules like (1). (1) If ‚ is a pronoun and i an index, then for any assignment g, [[‚i ]]g = g(i) (or undefined, if i is not in the domain of g). If one or more ê-features are present, these are adjoined to the indexed node (in an arbitrary hierarchical order). (2) [3rd [singular [masculine [he7 ]]]] Each feature denotes a partial identity function of type e,e. For gender, these are: (3) [[masculine]] = Îxe : x is male. x [[feminine]] = Îxe : x is female. x The constituent consisting of the feature and its complement is interpreted by Functional Application. It denotes an individual only if the denotation of the complement happens to have the relevant property (maleness or femaleness). When it does denote, it denotes the same individual. The partiality of the interpretation function is inherited up the tree and ultimately induces truthvalue gaps for the containing sentence. In a simplified example (omitting person and number), we compute the following result. (4) For any g: [[masc-he7 is married]]g is defined if 7 ∈ dom(g) and g(7) is male. Where defined, [[masc-he7 is married]]g = 1 if g(7) is married, and = 0 otherwise. If we are dealing with an unembedded occurrence of this sentence, uttered by a speaker who intends the 7th variable to refer to John, this means that the speaker is presupposing John to be male and asserting him to be married. This is Cooper’s treatment of gender features, and it can be extended straightforwardly to person and number 1 (notwithstanding the prevailing tradition in philosophy to analyze first person pronouns as indexicals rather than variables). We can treat all pronouns, regardless of person and number, as variables, hence subscripted by a numerical index and interpreted by rule (1). The various features attached to this index all denote partial identity functions. For number features, we need an ontology that has pluralities as well as simple objects among its individuals and supports appropriate notions 1 See, e.g., Dowty and Jacobson (1989), Schlenker (2002), Sauerland (2003). Features on Bound Pronouns 37 of atomicity and inclusion. Person features happen to be indexicals, 2 that is, they denote functions defined with reference to an utterance context that determines participant roles such as speaker and addressee. 3 I use “sc ”, “hc ” as abbreviations for “the speaker (addressee) of c.” number: [[singular]] = Îxe : x is an atom. x [[plural]] = Îxe : x is a plurality. x (5) person: [[1st]]c = Îxe : x includes sc . x [[2nd]]c = Îxe : x includes hc and excludes sc . x [[3rd]]c = Îxe : x excludes sc and hc . x For a first person singular pronoun, we compute the following presupposition and assertion. LF: I7 am married, spoken in a context c, asserts that gc (7) is married, and presupposes that gc (7) is an atom including sc . (6) Given the background ontology, an atom that includes the speaker can only be the speaker himself. So if the speaker of (6) manifestly intends to refer with I to himself, the presupposition in (6) is (trivially) true. If he manifestly intended to refer to someone else, it would be obviously false. Since it is impossible to presuppose an obvious falsehood, this cannot happen. Thus I always refers to the speaker, despite being technically a variable. 2.1.2 Features on bound-variable pronouns We have seen how ê-features on deictic pronouns, via their presuppositions, constrain the range of possible referents. Turning now to anaphoric, and specifically bound-variable, pronouns, it is not immediately obvious that the role of ê-features is the same. Reference, after all, is beside the point here, and the most salient job that ê-features appear to be performing is to constrain the range of possible antecedents. This is reflected in the grammaticality contrasts we obtain by varying ê-features of an obligatorily anaphoric pronoun such as the English self -reflexive. (7) Mary invited herself/*himself/*myself/*themselves. From a theoretical point of view, it would be disappointing to have different analyses of the same features depending on whether they are on deictic or anaphoric pronouns. And as we are about to see, there is good reason to 2 3 Notice that this is not the same thing as treating the pronoun itself as an indexical. See, e.g., Zwicky (1977) and Noyer (1992) for analyses of the morphosemantics of person. 38 Irene Heim believe that this undesirable maneuver is also unnecessary. The antecedentconstraining role of ê-features on anaphoric pronouns will be seen as a sideeffect of their basic reference-constraining semantics. 4 The LF of one of the ungrammatical versions of (7) must display the coindexing in (8) to satisfy Binding Theory. (8) Mary 5[t5 invited MASC5 ] What happens in the semantics? We first derive that the open sentence t 5 invited MASC5 denotes a truth value only under those assignments that map 5 to a male. Next we apply Predicate Abstraction, which in a system with truthvalue gaps is naturally formulated as follows. 5 (9) [[i ·]]g = Îxe : · ∈ dom([[ ]]gx/i ). [[·]]gx/i The predicate 5[t5 invited masc5 ] in (8) then denotes the partial function whose domain is males and which maps those who invited themselves to 1 and the others to 0 (in symbols, [Îxe : x is male. x invited x]). In the final step, we apply this function to Mary, which is only possible if Mary is male. So we predict that (8) presupposes that Mary is male. The asterisk in (7) reflects the judgment that “Mary invited himself ” is deviant under normal assumptions, namely when (the relevant) Mary is assumed to be a female. To the extent that the possibility of “Mary” naming a man is considered, the deviance judgment is qualified—as we predict. We saw already in this simple example that when we apply our presuppositional treatment of ê-features to bound-variable pronouns, we must complement it with a suitable theory of “presupposition projection”. In our setting, this amounts to formulating composition rules and lexical entries so they handle partiality in their inputs and pass it up appropriately to their outputs. Specifically, we need the formulation of Predicate Abstraction in (9), and— as we will see next—the right lexical entries for quantifying determiners. Consider a quantified variant of (7). (10) a. *Every girl invited himself. b. LF: every girl 5[t5 invited masc5 ] To interpret this, we must know how the generalized quantifier every girl applies to the partial function denoted by its sister. An appropriate entry is (11), predicting for (10a) the presupposition that every girl is male. 4 This is the main point of Cooper’s chapter on “Gender agreement” (ch. 7 of Cooper 1983). Dowty & Jacobson (1989) push Cooper’s approach further by considering number and person and by applying it also to the agreement between subjects and verbs. 5 See Heim and Kratzer (1998), where this formulation is motivated by examples of definite descriptions inside relative clauses. Features on Bound Pronouns 39 (11) [[every]] = Îfe,t . Îge,t : {x: f(x) = 1} ⊆ dom(g). {x: f(x) = 1} ⊆ {x: g(x) = 1} Again, this corresponds to the relevant judgment about (10): a deviant utterance under normal assumptions about the world. A consequence of this approach (highlighted by Cooper) is that common nouns need not be marked for gender. For example, the explanation just given for the deviance of (10) did not rely on the assumption that the noun girl was feminine—only on the assumption that girls are female. 6 This helps account for nouns that can antecede pronouns of either gender. Both (12) and (13) are non-deviant, but one is appropriate if the class is all male and the other if it is all female. (12) Every student in my class voted for himself. (13) Every student in my class voted for herself. We derive this from the assumptions we used in the analysis of (10). Example (12) presupposes that every student in my class is male, and (13) that every one is female. Cooper’s way of capturing gender mismatches between a bound pronoun and its binder as presupposition failures can also be applied to person and number mismatches. We derive impossible presuppositions also for (14) and (15). (14) *Every girl voted for themselves. LF: every girl 5[t5 voted for 3rd-pl5 ] predicted presupposition: “every girl is a plurality” (15) *Every girl voted for myself. LF: every girl 5[t5 voted for 1st-sg5 ] predicted presupposition: “every girl is identical to sc ” 7 A worry may arise of how the account applies to the non-quantified version of (15), which is no better. (16) *Mary invited myself. LF: Mary 5[t5 invited sg-1st